Difference between revisions of "Reductio Ad Absurdum"

From Conservapedia
Jump to: navigation, search
Line 1: Line 1:
'''Reductio ad absurdum''', also called [[proof]] by contradiction, is a method of mathematical proof.  It involves assuming the opposite of what one is trying to prove, and showing that this would lead to a contradiction. It works by the law of the excluded middle. The proof typically follows this structure:
+
'''Reductio ad absurdum''', also called '''proof by contradiction''', is a method of [[mathematical proof]].  It involves assuming the opposite of what one is trying to [[prove]], and showing that this would lead to a [[contradiction]]. It works by the [[law of the excluded middle]]. The proof typically follows this structure:
  
 
#Create an initial assumption
 
#Create an initial assumption
Line 6: Line 6:
 
#Therefore the initial assumption is incorrect
 
#Therefore the initial assumption is incorrect
  
An example of this is [[Euclid]]'s proof of the infinitude of the [[Prime number|primes]]:
+
An example of this is [[Euclid]]'s proof of the [[infinitude]] of the [[Prime number|primes]]:
  
 
#Assume there are finitely many primes
 
#Assume there are finitely many primes

Revision as of 17:59, June 30, 2008

Reductio ad absurdum, also called proof by contradiction, is a method of mathematical proof. It involves assuming the opposite of what one is trying to prove, and showing that this would lead to a contradiction. It works by the law of the excluded middle. The proof typically follows this structure:

  1. Create an initial assumption
  2. Follow a series of axiomatically valid steps
  3. Reach a contradiction
  4. Therefore the initial assumption is incorrect

An example of this is Euclid's proof of the infinitude of the primes:

  1. Assume there are finitely many primes
  2. Take the product of all primes and call it N. Since N+1 is not in our finite set of primes, it must be composite
  3. By the fundamental theorem of arithmetic, N+1 has a prime factorization. But N+1 is not divisible by any of the previous primes
  4. Since N+1 is composite, there must be a prime missing from our set of primes. But this set contains all primes
  5. Therefore, our initial assumption ("there are finitely many primes") is invalid